From 68734ddaf771fb862bbb612dcac697c2ebb8fd9b Mon Sep 17 00:00:00 2001 From: Ralf Jung <jung@mpi-sws.org> Date: Mon, 10 Oct 2016 11:03:22 +0200 Subject: [PATCH] docs: complete section on composeable dynamic ghost ownership --- docs/ghost-state.tex | 65 ++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++------ 1 file changed, 57 insertions(+), 8 deletions(-) diff --git a/docs/ghost-state.tex b/docs/ghost-state.tex index 13f66fb83..21769c81a 100644 --- a/docs/ghost-state.tex +++ b/docs/ghost-state.tex @@ -1,22 +1,28 @@ \section{Composeable Dynamic Higher-Order Resources} \label{sec:hogs} -The logic described in \Sref{sec:base-logic} works over an arbitrary CMRA $\monoid$ defining the structure of the resources. +The base logic described in \Sref{sec:base-logic} works over an arbitrary CMRA $\monoid$ defining the structure of the resources. It turns out that we can generalize this further and permit picking CMRAs ``$\iFunc(\Prop)$'' that depend on the structure of assertions themselves. Of course, $\Prop$ is just the syntactic type of assertions; for this to make sense we have to look at the semantics. -Furthermore, there is a composeability problem with the given logic: if we have one proof performed with CMRA $\monoid_1$, and another proof carried out with a \emph{different} CMRA $\monoid_2$, then the two proofs are actually carried out in two entirely separate logics and hence cannot be combined. +Furthermore, there is a composeability problem with the given logic: if we have one proof performed with CMRA $\monoid_1$, and another proof carried out with a \emph{different} CMRA $\monoid_2$, then the two proofs are actually carried out in two \emph{entirely separate logics} and hence cannot be combined. -The purpose of this section is to describe how we solve these two issues. +Finally, in many cases just having a single ``instance'' of a CMRA available for reasoning is not enough. +For example, when reasoning about a dynamically allocated data structure, every time a new instance of that data structure is created, we will want a fresh resource governing the state of this particular instance. +While it would be possible to handle this problem whenever it comes up, it turns out to be useful to provide a general solution. -\subsection{Multiple CMRAs and Higher-Order Resources} +The purpose of this section is to describe how we solve these issues. -To instantiate the logic, you pick a \emph{family} of locally contractive bifunctors $(\iFunc_i : \COFEs \to \CMRAs)_{i \in \mathcal{I}}$. +\paragraph{Picking the resources.} +The key ingredient that we will employ on top of the base logic is to give some more fixed structure to the resources. +To instantiate the composeable, dynamic logic, the user picks a family of locally contractive bifunctors $(\iFunc_i : \COFEs \to \CMRAs)_{i \in \mathcal{I}}$. +(This is in contrast to the base logic, where the user picks a single, fixed CMRA that has a unit.) From this, we construct the bifunctor defining the overall resources as follows: \begin{align*} \textdom{ResF}(\cofe^\op, \cofe) \eqdef{}& \prod_{i \in \mathcal I} \mathbb{N} \fpfn \iFunc_i(\cofe^\op, \cofe) \end{align*} +(We will motivate both the use of a product and the finite partial function below.) $\textdom{ResF}(\cofe^\op, \cofe)$ is a CMRA by lifting the individual CMRAs pointwise, and it has a unit (using the empty finite partial functions). Furthermore, since the $\iFunc_i$ are locally contractive, so is $\textdom{ResF}$. @@ -33,13 +39,56 @@ We only need the isomorphism, given by \wIso^{-1} &: \iPreProp \nfn \iProp \end{align*} -Notice that $\iProp$ is the semantic model of assertions for the logic described in \Sref{sec:base-logic} with $\Res$: +Notice that $\iProp$ is the semantic model of assertions for the base logic described in \Sref{sec:base-logic} with $\Res$: \[ \Sem{\Prop} \eqdef \iProp = \UPred(\Res) \] +Effectively, we just defined a way to instantiate the base logic with $\Res$ as the CMRA of resources, while providing a way for $\Res$ to depend on $\iPreProp$, which is isomorphic to $\Sem\Prop$. + We thus obtain all the rules of \Sref{sec:base-logic}, and furthermore, we can use the maps $\wIso$ and $\wIso^{-1}$ \emph{in the logic} to convert between logical assertions $\Sem\Prop$ and the domain $\iPreProp$ which is used in the construction of $\Res$ -- so from elements of $\iPreProp$, we can construct elements of $\Sem{\textlog M}$, which are the elements that can be owned in our logic. -\ralf{TODO: Describe the pattern of only assuming some elements of the index family to indicate a particular functor.} -\ralf{TODO: Show the rules for ownership in this world.} +\paragraph{Proof composeability.} +To make our proofs composeable, we \emph{generalize} our proofs over the family of functors. +This is possible because we made $\Res$ a \emph{product} of all the CMRAs picked by the user, and because we can actually work with that product ``pointwise''. +So instead of picking a \emph{concrete} family, proofs will assume to be given an \emph{arbitrary} family of functors, plus a proof that this family \emph{contains the functors they need}. +Composing two proofs is then merely a matter of conjoining the assumptions they make about the functors. +Since the logic is entirely parametric in the choice of functors, there is no trouble reasoning without full knowledge of the family of functors. + +Only when the top-level proof is completed we will ``close'' the proof by picking a concrete family that contains exactly those functors the proof needs. + +\paragraph{Dynamic resources.} +Finally, the use of finite partial functions lets us have as many instances of any CMRA as we could wish for: +Because there can only ever be finitely many instances already allocated, it is always possible to create a fresh instance with any desired (valid) starting state. +This is best demonstrated by giving some proof rules. + +So let us first define the notion of ghost ownership that we use in this logic. +Assuming that the family of functors contains the functor $\Sigma_i$ at index $i$, and furthermore assuming that $\monoid_i = \Sigma_i(\iPreProp, \iPreProp)$, given some $\melt \in \monoid_i$ we define: +\[ \ownGhost\gname{\melt:\monoid_i} \eqdef \ownM{(\ldots, \emptyset, i:\set{\gname \mapsto \melt}, \emptyset, \ldots)} \] +This is ownership of the pair (element of the product over all the functors) that has the empty finite partial function in all components \emph{except for} the component corresponding to index $i$, where we own the element $\melt$ at index $\gname$ in the finite partial function. + +We can show the following properties for this form of ownership: +\begin{mathparpagebreakable} + \inferH{res-alloc}{\text{$G$ infinite} \and \melt \in \mval_{M_i}} + { \TRUE \proves \upd \Exists\gname\in G. \ownGhost\gname{\melt : M_i} + } + \and + \inferH{res-update} + {\melt \mupd_{M_i} B} + {\ownGhost\gname{\melt : M_i} \proves \upd \Exists \meltB\in B. \ownGhost\gname{\meltB : M_i}} + + \inferH{res-empty} + {\text{$\munit$ is a unit of $M_i$}} + {\TRUE \proves \upd \ownGhost\gname\munit} + + \axiomH{res-op} + {\ownGhost\gname{\melt : M_i} * \ownGhost\gname{\meltB : M_i} \provesIff \ownGhost\gname{\melt\mtimes\meltB : M_i}} + + \axiomH{res-valid} + {\ownGhost\gname{\melt : M_i} \Ra \mval_{M_i}(\melt)} + +\end{mathparpagebreakable} +Below, we will always work in the context of this dynamic, composeable logic. +Whenever a CMRA is used in a proof, we implicitly assume it to be available in the global family of functors. +We will typically leave the $M_i$ implicit when asserting ghost ownership, as the type of $\melt$ will be clear from the context. -- GitLab