Newer
Older
% !TEX root = ./appendix.tex
\section{CMRA constructions}
\subsection{Agreement}
Given some COFE $\cofe$, we define $\agm(\cofe)$ as follows:
\begin{align*}
\monoid \eqdef{}& \recordComp{c : \mathbb{N} \to T , V : \pset{\mathbb{N}}}{ \All n, m. n \geq m \Ra n \in V \Ra m \in V } \\
\melt \equiv \meltB \eqdef{}& \melt.V = \meltB.V \land \All n. n \in \melt.V \Ra \melt.c(n) \nequiv{n} \meltB.c(n) \\
\melt \nequiv{n} \meltB \eqdef{}& (\All m \leq n. m \in \melt.V \Lra m \in \meltB.V) \land (\All m \leq n. m \in \melt.V \Ra \melt.c(m) \nequiv{m} \meltB.c(m)) \\
\mval_n \eqdef{}& \setComp{\melt \in \monoid}{ n \in \melt.V \land \All m \leq n. \melt.c(n) \nequiv{m} \melt.c(m) } \\
\melt \mtimes \meltB \eqdef{}& (\melt.c, \setComp{n}{n \in \melt.V \land n \in \meltB.V_2 \land \melt \nequiv{n} \meltB })
\end{align*}
$\agm(-)$ is a locally non-expansive bifunctor from $\COFEs$ to $\CMRAs$.
The reason we store a \emph{chain} $c$ of elements of $T$, rather than a single element, is that $\agm(\cofe)$ needs to be a COFE itself, so we need to be able to give a limit for every chain.
\ralf{Figure out why exactly this is not possible without adding an explicit chain here.}
There are no interesting frame-preserving updates for $\agm(\cofe)$, but we can show the following:
\begin{mathpar}
\axiomH{ag-dup}{\melt = \melt \mtimes \melt}
\and\axiomH{ag-agree}{\melt \mtimes \meltB \in \mval_n \Ra \melt \nequiv{n} \meltB}
\end{mathpar}
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
% \subsection{Exclusive monoid}
% Given a set $X$, we define a monoid such that at most one $x \in X$ can be owned.
% Let $\exm{X}$ be the monoid with carrier $X \uplus \{ \munit \}$ and multiplication
% \[
% \melt \cdot \meltB \;\eqdef\;
% \begin{cases}
% \melt & \mbox{if } \meltB = \munit \\
% \meltB & \mbox{if } \melt = \munit
% \end{cases}
% \]
% The frame-preserving update
% \begin{mathpar}
% \inferH{ExUpd}
% {x \in X}
% {x \mupd \melt}
% \end{mathpar}
% is easily shown, as the only possible frame for $x$ is $\munit$.
% Exclusive monoids are cancellative.
% \begin{proof}[Proof of cancellativity]
% If $\melt_f = \munit$, then the statement is trivial.
% If $\melt_f \neq \munit$, then we must have $\melt = \meltB = \munit$, as otherwise one of the two products would be $\mzero$.
% \end{proof}
% \subsection{Agreement monoid}
% Given a set $X$, we define a monoid such that everybody agrees on which $x \in X$ has been chosen.
% Let $\agm{X}$ be the monoid with carrier $X \uplus \{ \munit \}$ and multiplication
% \[
% \melt \cdot \meltB \;\eqdef\;
% \begin{cases}
% \melt & \mbox{if } \meltB = \munit \lor \melt = \meltB \\
% \meltB & \mbox{if } \melt = \munit
% \end{cases}
% \]
% Agreement monoids are cancellative.
% \begin{proof}[Proof of cancellativity]
% If $\melt_f = \munit$, then the statement is trivial.
% If $\melt_f \neq \munit$, then if $\melt = \munit$, we must have $\meltB = \munit$ and we are done.
% Similar so for $\meltB = \munit$.
% So let $\melt \neq \munit \neq \meltB$ and $\melt_f \mtimes \melt = \melt_f \mtimes \meltB \neq \mzero$.
% It follows immediately that $\melt = \melt_f = \meltB$.
% \end{proof}
% \subsection{Finite Powerset Monoid}
% Given an infinite set $X$, we define a monoid $\textmon{PowFin}$ with carrier $\mathcal{P}^{\textrm{fin}}(X)$ as follows:
% \[
% \melt \cdot \meltB \;\eqdef\; \melt \cup \meltB \quad \mbox{if } \melt \cap \meltB = \emptyset
% \]
% We obtain:
% \begin{mathpar}
% \inferH{PowFinUpd}{}
% {\emptyset \mupd \{ \{x\} \mid x \in X \}}
% \end{mathpar}
% \begin{proof}[Proof of \ruleref{PowFinUpd}]
% Assume some frame $\melt_f \sep \emptyset$. Since $\melt_f$ is finite and $X$ is infinite, there exists an $x \notin \melt_f$.
% Pick that for the result.
% \end{proof}
% The powerset monoids is cancellative.
% \begin{proof}[Proof of cancellativity]
% Let $\melt_f \mtimes \melt = \melt_f \mtimes \meltB \neq \mzero$.
% So we have $\melt_f \sep \melt$ and $\melt_f \sep \meltB$, and we have to show $\melt = \meltB$.
% Assume $x \in \melt$. Hence $x \in \melt_f \mtimes \melt$ and thus $x \in \melt_f \mtimes \meltB$.
% By disjointness, $x \notin \melt_f$ and hence $x \in meltB$.
% The other direction works the same way.
% \end{proof}
% \subsection{Product monoid}
% \label{sec:prodm}
% Given a family $(M_i)_{i \in I}$ of monoids ($I$ countable), we construct a product monoid.
% Let $\prod_{i \in I} M_i$ be the monoid with carrier $\prod_{i \in I} \mcarp{M_i}$ and point-wise multiplication, non-zero when \emph{all} individual multiplications are non-zero.
% For $f \in \prod_{i \in I} \mcarp{M_i}$, we write $f[i \mapsto a]$ for the disjoint union $f \uplus [i \mapsto a]$.
% Frame-preserving updates on the $M_i$ lift to the product:
% \begin{mathpar}
% \inferH{ProdUpd}
% {a \mupd_{M_i} B}
% {f[i \mapsto a] \mupd \{ f[i \mapsto b] \mid b \in B\}}
% \end{mathpar}
% \begin{proof}[Proof of \ruleref{ProdUpd}]
% Assume some frame $g$ and let $c \eqdef g(i)$.
% Since $f[i \mapsto a] \sep g$, we get $f \sep g$ and $a \sep_{M_i} c$.
% Thus there exists $b \in B$ such that $b \sep_{M_i} c$.
% It suffices to show $f[i \mapsto b] \sep g$.
% Since multiplication is defined pointwise, this is the case if all components are compatible.
% For $i$, we know this from $b \sep_{M_i} c$.
% For all the other components, from $f \sep g$.
% \end{proof}
% If every $M_i$ is cancellative, then so is $\prod_{i \in I} M_i$.
% \begin{proof}[Proof of cancellativity]
% Let $\melt, \meltB, \melt_f \in \prod_{i \in I} \mcarp{M_i}$, and assume $\melt_f \mtimes \melt = \melt_f \mtimes \meltB \neq \mzero$.
% By the definition of multiplication, this means that for all $i \in I$ we have $\melt_f(i) \mtimes \melt(i) = \melt_f(i) \mtimes \meltB(i) \neq \mzero_{M_i}$.
% As all base monoids are cancellative, we obtain $\forall i \in I.\; \melt(i) = \meltB(i)$ from which we immediately get $\melt = \meltB$.
% \end{proof}
% \subsection{Fractional monoid}
% \label{sec:fracm}
% Given a monoid $M$, we define a monoid representing fractional ownership of some piece $\melt \in M$.
% The idea is to preserve all the frame-preserving update that $M$ could have, while additionally being able to do \emph{any} update if we own the full state (as determined by the fraction being $1$).
% Let $\fracm{M}$ be the monoid with carrier $(((0, 1] \cap \mathbb{Q}) \times M) \uplus \{\munit\}$ and multiplication
% \begin{align*}
% (q, a) \mtimes (q', a') &\eqdef (q + q', a \mtimes a') \qquad \mbox{if $q+q'\le 1$} \\
% (q, a) \mtimes \munit &\eqdef (q,a) \\
% \munit \mtimes (q,a) &\eqdef (q,a).
% \end{align*}
% We get the following frame-preserving update.
% \begin{mathpar}
% \inferH{FracUpdFull}
% {a, b \in M}
% {(1, a) \mupd (1, b)}
% \and\inferH{FracUpdLocal}
% {a \mupd_M B}
% {(q, a) \mupd \{q\} \times B}
% \end{mathpar}
% \begin{proof}[Proof of \ruleref{FracUpdFull}]
% Assume some $f \sep (1, a)$. This can only be $f = \munit$, so showing $f \sep (1, b)$ is trivial.
% \end{proof}
% \begin{proof}[Proof of \ruleref{FracUpdLocal}]
% Assume some $f \sep (q, a)$. If $f = \munit$, then $f \sep (q, b)$ is trivial for any $b \in B$. Just pick the one we obtain by choosing $\munit_M$ as the frame for $a$.
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
287
288
289
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
316
317
318
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
339
340
341
342
343
344
345
346
347
348
349
350
351
352
353
354
355
356
357
358
359
360
361
362
363
364
365
366
367
368
369
370
371
372
373
% In the interesting case, we have $f = (q_f, a_f)$.
% Obtain $b$ such that $b \in B \land b \sep a_f$.
% Then $(q, b) \sep f$, and we are done.
% \end{proof}
% $\fracm{M}$ is cancellative if $M$ is cancellative.
% \begin{proof}[Proof of cancellativitiy]
% If $\melt_f = \munit$, we are trivially done.
% So let $\melt_f = (q_f, \melt_f')$.
% If $\melt = \munit$, then $\meltB = \munit$ as otherwise the fractions could not match up.
% Again, we are trivially done.
% Similar so for $\meltB = \munit$.
% So let $\melt = (q_a, \melt')$ and $\meltB = (q_b, \meltB')$.
% We have $(q_f + q_a, \melt_f' \mtimes \melt') = (q_f + q_b, \melt_f' \mtimes \meltB')$.
% We have to show $q_a = q_b$ and $\melt' = \meltB'$.
% The first is trivial, the second follows from cancellativitiy of $M$.
% \end{proof}
% \subsection{Finite partial function monoid}
% \label{sec:fpfunm}
% Given a countable set $X$ and a monoid $M$, we construct a monoid representing finite partial functions from $X$ to (non-unit, non-zero elements of) $M$.
% \ralf{all outdated}
% Let ${X} \fpfn {M}$ be the product monoid $\prod_{x \in X} M$, as defined in \secref{sec:prodm} but restricting the carrier to functions $f$ where the set $\dom(f) \eqdef \{ x \mid f(x) \neq \munit_M \}$ is finite.
% This is well-defined as the set of these $f$ contains the unit and is closed under multiplication.
% (We identify finite partial functions from $X$ to $\mcarp{M}\setminus\{\munit_M\}$ and total functions from $X$ to $\mcarp{M}$ with finite $\munit_M$-support.)
% We use two frame-preserving updates:
% \begin{mathpar}
% \inferH{FpFunAlloc}
% {a \in \mcarp{M}}
% {f \mupd \{ f[x \mapsto a] \mid x \notin \dom(f) \}}
% \and
% \inferH{FpFunUpd}
% {a \mupd_M B}
% {f[i \mapsto a] \mupd \{ f[i \mapsto b] \mid b \in B\}}
% \end{mathpar}
% Rule \ruleref{FpFunUpd} simply restates \ruleref{ProdUpd}.
% \begin{proof}[Proof of \ruleref{FpFunAlloc}]
% Assume some $g \sep f$. Since $\dom(f \mtimes g)$ is finite, there will be some undefined element $x \notin \dom(f \mtimes g)$. Let $f' \eqdef f[x \mapsto a]$. This is compatible with $g$, so we are done.
% \end{proof}
% We write $[x \mapsto a]$ for the function mapping $x$ to $a$ and everything else in $X$ to $\munit$.
% %\subsection{Disposable monoid}
% %
% %Given a monoid $M$, we construct a monoid where, having full ownership of an element $\melt$ of $M$, one can throw it away, transitioning to a dead element.
% %Let \dispm{M} be the monoid with carrier $\mcarp{M} \uplus \{ \disposed \}$ and multiplication
% %% The previous unit must remain the unit of the new monoid, as is is always duplicable and hence we could not transition to \disposed if it were not composable with \disposed
% %\begin{align*}
% % \melt \mtimes \meltB &\eqdef \melt \mtimes_M \meltB & \IF \melt \sep[M] \meltB \\
% % \disposed \mtimes \disposed &\eqdef \disposed \\
% % \munit_M \mtimes \disposed &\eqdef \disposed \mtimes \munit_M \eqdef \disposed
% %\end{align*}
% %The unit is the same as in $M$.
% %
% %The frame-preserving updates are
% %\begin{mathpar}
% % \inferH{DispUpd}
% % {a \in \mcarp{M} \setminus \{\munit_M\} \and a \mupd_M B}
% % {a \mupd B}
% % \and
% % \inferH{Dispose}
% % {a \in \mcarp{M} \setminus \{\munit_M\} \and \All b \in \mcarp{M}. a \sep b \Ra b = \munit_M}
% % {a \mupd \disposed}
% %\end{mathpar}
% %
% %\begin{proof}[Proof of \ruleref{DispUpd}]
% %Assume a frame $f$. If $f = \disposed$, then $a = \munit_M$, which is a contradiction.
% %Thus $f \in \mcarp{M}$ and we can use $a \mupd_M B$.
% %\end{proof}
% %
% %\begin{proof}[Proof of \ruleref{Dispose}]
% %The second premiss says that $a$ has no non-trivial frame in $M$. To show the update, assume a frame $f$ in $\dispm{M}$. Like above, we get $f \in \mcarp{M}$, and thus $f = \munit_M$. But $\disposed \sep \munit_M$ is trivial, so we are done.
% %\end{proof}
% \subsection{Authoritative monoid}\label{sec:auth}
% Given a monoid $M$, we construct a monoid modeling someone owning an \emph{authoritative} element $x$ of $M$, and others potentially owning fragments $\melt \le_M x$ of $x$.
% (If $M$ is an exclusive monoid, the construction is very similar to a half-ownership monoid with two asymmetric halves.)
% Let $\auth{M}$ be the monoid with carrier
% \[
% \setComp{ (x, \melt) }{ x \in \mcarp{\exm{\mcarp{M}}} \land \melt \in \mcarp{M} \land (x = \munit_{\exm{\mcarp{M}}} \lor \melt \leq_M x) }
% \]
% and multiplication
% \[
% (x, \melt) \mtimes (y, \meltB) \eqdef
% (x \mtimes y, \melt \mtimes \meltB) \quad \mbox{if } x \sep y \land \melt \sep \meltB \land (x \mtimes y = \munit_{\exm{\mcarp{M}}} \lor \melt \mtimes \meltB \leq_M x \mtimes y)
% \]
% Note that $(\munit_{\exm{\mcarp{M}}}, \munit_M)$ is the unit and asserts no ownership whatsoever, but $(\munit_{M}, \munit_M)$ asserts that the authoritative element is $\munit_M$.
% Let $x, \melt \in \mcarp M$.
% We write $\authfull x$ for full ownership $(x, \munit_M):\auth{M}$ and $\authfrag \melt$ for fragmental ownership $(\munit_{\exm{\mcarp{M}}}, \melt)$ and $\authfull x , \authfrag \melt$ for combined ownership $(x, \melt)$.
% If $x$ or $a$ is $\mzero_{M}$, then the sugar denotes $\mzero_{\auth{M}}$.
% \ralf{This needs syncing with the Coq development.}
% The frame-preserving update involves a rather unwieldy side-condition:
% \begin{mathpar}
% \inferH{AuthUpd}{
% \All\melt_f\in\mcar{\monoid}. \melt\sep\meltB \land \melt\mtimes\melt_f \le \meltB\mtimes\melt_f \Ra \melt'\mtimes\melt_f \le \melt'\mtimes\meltB \and
% \melt' \sep \meltB
% }{
% \authfull \melt \mtimes \meltB, \authfrag \melt \mupd \authfull \melt' \mtimes \meltB, \authfrag \melt'
% }
% \end{mathpar}
% We therefore derive two special cases.
% \paragraph{Local frame-preserving updates.}
% \newcommand\authupd{f}%
% Following~\cite{scsl}, we say that $\authupd: \mcar{M} \ra \mcar{M}$ is \emph{local} if
% \[
% \All a, b \in \mcar{M}. a \sep b \land \authupd(a) \neq \mzero \Ra \authupd(a \mtimes b) = \authupd(a) \mtimes b
% \]
% Then,
% \begin{mathpar}
% \inferH{AuthUpdLocal}
% {\text{$\authupd$ local} \and \authupd(\melt)\sep\meltB}
% {\authfull \melt \mtimes \meltB, \authfrag \melt \mupd \authfull \authupd(\melt) \mtimes \meltB, \authfrag \authupd(\melt)}
% \end{mathpar}
% \paragraph{Frame-preserving updates on cancellative monoids.}
% Frame-preserving updates are also possible if we assume $M$ cancellative:
% \begin{mathpar}
% \inferH{AuthUpdCancel}
% {\text{$M$ cancellative} \and \melt'\sep\meltB}
% {\authfull \melt \mtimes \meltB, \authfrag \melt \mupd \authfull \melt' \mtimes \meltB, \authfrag \melt'}
% \end{mathpar}
% \subsection{Fractional heap monoid}
% \label{sec:fheapm}
% By combining the fractional, finite partial function, and authoritative monoids, we construct two flavors of heaps with fractional permissions and mention their important frame-preserving updates.
% Hereinafter, we assume the set $\textdom{Val}$ of values is countable.
% Given a set $Y$, define $\FHeap(Y) \eqdef \textdom{Val} \fpfn \fracm(Y)$ representing a fractional heap with codomain $Y$.
% From \S\S\ref{sec:fracm} and~\ref{sec:fpfunm} we obtain the following frame-preserving updates as well as the fact that $\FHeap(Y)$ is cancellative.
% \begin{mathpar}
% \axiomH{FHeapUpd}{h[x \mapsto (1, y)] \mupd h[x \mapsto (1, y')]} \and
% \axiomH{FHeapAlloc}{h \mupd \{\, h[x \mapsto (1, y)] \mid x \in \textdom{Val} \,\}}
% \end{mathpar}
% We will write $qh$ with $h : \textsort{Val} \fpfn Y$ for the function in $\FHeap(Y)$ mapping every $x \in \dom(h)$ to $(q, h(x))$, and everything else to $\munit$.
% Define $\AFHeap(Y) \eqdef \auth{\FHeap(Y)}$ representing an authoritative fractional heap with codomain $Y$.
% We easily obtain the following frame-preserving updates.
% \begin{mathpar}
% \axiomH{AFHeapUpd}{
% (\authfull h[x \mapsto (1, y)], \authfrag [x \mapsto (1, y)]) \mupd (\authfull h[x \mapsto (1, y')], \authfrag [x \mapsto (1, y')])
% }
% \and
% \inferH{AFHeapAdd}{
% x \notin \dom(h)
% }{
% \authfull h \mupd (\authfull h[x \mapsto (q, y)], \authfrag [x \mapsto (q, y)])
% }
% \and
% \axiomH{AFHeapRemove}{
% (\authfull h[x \mapsto (q, y)], \authfrag [x \mapsto (q, y)]) \mupd \authfull h
% }
% \end{mathpar}
% \subsection{STS with tokens monoid}
% \label{sec:stsmon}
% \ralf{This needs syncing with the Coq development.}
% Given a state-transition system~(STS) $(\STSS, \ra)$, a set of tokens $\STSS$, and a labeling $\STSL: \STSS \ra \mathcal{P}(\STST)$ of \emph{protocol-owned} tokens for each state, we construct a monoid modeling an authoritative current state and permitting transitions given a \emph{bound} on the current state and a set of \emph{locally-owned} tokens.
% The construction follows the idea of STSs as described in CaReSL \cite{caresl}.
% We first lift the transition relation to $\STSS \times \mathcal{P}(\STST)$ (implementing a \emph{law of token conservation}) and define upwards closure:
% \begin{align*}
% (s, T) \ra (s', T') \eqdef&\, s \ra s' \land \STSL(s) \uplus T = \STSL(s') \uplus T' \\
% \textsf{frame}(s, T) \eqdef&\, (s, \STST \setminus (\STSL(s) \uplus T)) \\
% \upclose(S, T) \eqdef&\, \setComp{ s' \in \STSS}{\exists s \in S.\; \textsf{frame}(s, T) \ststrans \textsf{frame}(s', T) }
% \end{align*}
% \noindent
% We have
% \begin{quote}
% If $(s, T) \ra (s', T')$\\
% and $T_f \sep (T \uplus \STSL(s))$,\\
% then $\textsf{frame}(s, T_f) \ra \textsf{frame}(s', T_f)$.
% \end{quote}
% \begin{proof}
% This follows directly by framing the tokens in $\STST \setminus (T_f \uplus T \uplus \STSL(s))$ around the given transition, which yields $(s, \STST \setminus (T_f \uplus \STSL{T}(s))) \ra (s', T' \uplus (\STST \setminus (T_f \uplus T \uplus \STSL{T}(s))))$.
% This is exactly what we have to show, since we know $\STSL(s) \uplus T = \STSL(s') \uplus T'$.
% \end{proof}
% Let $\STSMon{\STSS}$ be the monoid with carrier
% \[
% \setComp{ (s, S, T) \in \exm{\STSS} \times \mathcal{P}(\STSS) \times \mathcal{P}(\STST) }{ \begin{aligned} &(s = \munit \lor s \in S) \land \upclose(S, T) = S \land{} \\& S \neq \emptyset \land \All s \in S. \STSL(s) \sep T \end{aligned} }
% \]
% and multiplication
% \[
% (s, S, T) \mtimes (s', S', T') \eqdef (s'' \eqdef s \mtimes_{\exm{\STSS}} s', S'' \eqdef S \cap S', T'' \eqdef T \cup T') \quad \text{if }\begin{aligned}[t] &(s = \munit \lor s' = \munit) \land T \sep T' \land{} \\& S'' \neq \emptyset \land (s'' \neq \munit \Ra s'' \in S'') \end{aligned}
% \]
% Some sugar makes it more convenient to assert being at least in a certain state and owning some tokens: $(s, T) : \STSMon{\STSS} \eqdef (\munit, \upclose(\{s\}, T), T) : \STSMon{\STSS}$, and
% $s : \STSMon{\STSS} \eqdef (s, \emptyset) : \STSMon{\STSS}$.
% We will need the following frame-preserving update.
% \begin{mathpar}
% \inferH{StsStep}{(s, T) \ststrans (s', T')}
% {(s, S, T) \mupd (s', \upclose(\{s'\}, T'), T')}
% \end{mathpar}
% \begin{proof}[Proof of \ruleref{StsStep}]
% Assume some upwards-closed $S_f, T_f$ (the frame cannot be authoritative) s.t.\ $s \in S_f$ and $T_f \sep (T \uplus \STSL(s))$. We have to show that this frame combines with our final monoid element, which is the case if $s' \in S_f$ and $T_f \sep T'$.
% By upward-closedness, it suffices to show $\textsf{frame}(s, T_f) \ststrans \textsf{frame}(s', T_f)$.
% This follows by induction on the path $(s, T) \ststrans (s', T')$, and using the lemma proven above for each step.
% \end{proof}